Philosophy
210/310
Early Modern Philosophy
|
Two ways to think about ideas
Descartes continues to think about ideas, and realizes that we can think about ideas in two ways:
As modes of thinking things (i.e., as mental occurrences, as things that are happening in my mind. In this way they are like pains or tickles) Conceived of in this way, ideas stand to thinking things in just the way that shape and size stand to corporeal things.
As representations (i.e., as ideas of something). Conceived of in this way, ideas are pictures, they have content and meaning. They are about something.
An analogy: You can think of what is on the chalkboard as a collection of chalk dust, or as a picture of a tree. You can think of what you see on the walls of the museum as a mound of oil paint, or as a picture of a ship at sea. Similarly, you can think of ideas as mental happenings, or as representations.
Even though Descartes is certain only that he has ideas, he realizes that the ideas he has are representational. They can be considered as pictures of other things (of course, he's not certain there are other things, but that doesn't take away at all from the representational nature of his ideas.)
Some Heavy-Duty Metaphysical Apparatus
We need to set out some of Descartes' technical apparatus before we can appreciate his attempt to show that God's existence follows from the fact that he has an idea of God.
Kinds of Being
Consider the following little argument:
Of course, we all know that thinking about Pegasus (or a check, or the perfect mate) doesn't make them exist. But how are we to express this point without going back on the above argument? The solution is to draw a distinction. In this case, a distinction between two ways of existing, or being. There's the way of being that (the argument shows) Pegasus has, and there's the way of being that you and I and the Eiffel Tower have (and which the million-dollar check, and the perfect mate, and Pegasus don't have). Descartes, following the medieval practice, calls these "Objective Being" and "Formal Being"
Objective being: Being as an object of thought
Notice also that we can talk of things that have objective being only when we are thinking about ideas as pictures or representations. If they were merely modifications of the mind, then we could not talk about objective being. We could not, because we could not talk about an idea being about anything. To see ideas as having content or being about something is to see them as more than just modes of thinking things.
Degrees of Reality
The second piece of the puzzle is the idea that among the things that are real, some things may be more real than others. Reality, in other words, comes in degrees. This is a strange notion, for we are used to thinking of reality as an 'on-or-off' property: something either is real or is not. Though it sounds strange, it is less strange once you see what is really at stake in ordering things by the amount of reality that they have.
Properties vs Substances
I have a mint-green bookcase. Given this, we can say the following:
|
|
Two remarks before we go on:
The notion that properties cannot exist independently is not universally accepted. We saw a discussion of this in the Second Meditation, when we reconstructed the Cogito argument in terms of the Substance Theory. There we saw the possibility of a Platonist account of properties whereby properties can exist independently of substances. On this point, however, Descartes was no Platonist.
In accepting the idea that substances can exist independently, are we thereby saying that a substance can exist without any properties at all? No, for we should understand the discussion above to be making the point that particular substances can exist independently of particular properties (my bookcase need not be any particular color, but it must be some color or other; my bookcase need not be in any particular place, but it needs to be someplace or other), but a particular property exists only if some particular substance exhibits it.
Perfections of Substances
Now let's focus on the substances. There are a lot of them: stones, carrots, frogs, dogs, people, angels and even God. These are all substances--they all have independent existence. But once we start thinking about it, we notice that there are differences among these substances in terms of their capacities and abilities. What can stones do? Not much. They just take up space. They're about as basic a physical substance as you can get. Of course, carrots take up space, but they do more: they can grow and reproduce. Stones can't do that. If we think of independent existence, taking up space, growth, and reproduction as (to use the medieval term) "perfections", then we can say that carrots have more perfections than stones do. And we can continue in this way for the other substances. What we get is the following elaboration of our first picture:
God
all perfections & infinitely so
|
Angels
(below plus) immateriality
People (below plus) reason & self-awareness Dogs
(below plus) adaptability
Frogs (below plus) movement & communication Carrots (below plus) growth & reproduction Stones independent existence |
|
The thought here is that some substances have more perfections than other substances (people have more perfections than frogs but fewer perfections than angels), and in this sense, we can rank some substances as being "more real" than other substances.
So, what the notion of degrees of reality is adverting to are these two, reasonably plausible thoughts: (a) some things exist dependently, and others independently and (b) some things have more abilities, capacities, or (in our term) "perfections" than others.
Now, notice also that this discussion of degrees of reality is combinable with the earlier discussion about the two kinds of being, and in two important respects.
First, we can compare the degrees of reality exhibited by things that have objective being. We can say that my idea of Pegasus has more reality than my idea of the Eiffel Tower.
Second, and importantly for Descartes, we can compare degrees of reality across the kinds of being. We can say, for instance, that Pegasus has more objective reality than the Eiffel Tower has formal reality. Of course, my idea of Pegasus has less formal reality than the Eiffel Tower has formal reality. (Why? Because ideas are modes of thinking things--mere properties--and so lowest on the "Great Chain of Being".) But Pegasus has a lot of objective reality--more objective reality than the Eiffel Tower has formal reality.
"From nothing, nothing comes". This is an old principle--perhaps one of the oldest in Western philosophy, as it dates back to the pre-Socratic philosophers. The idea is a simple one: you can't get something from nothing.
For the English majors, this principle shows up in the first scene
of King Lear. As you'll recall, Lear asks his daughters to say how
much they love him, and in return he'll give them a piece of his kingdom.
His first two daughters have heaped on the praise, and Lear has rewarded
them handsomely. Now, Lear turns to his youngest and most-loved daughter,
Cordelia:
Lear: ...what can you say to draw a third more opulent than your sisters? Speak. Cordelia: Nothing, my lord. Lear: Nothing! Cordelia: Nothing. Lear: Nothing will come of nothing. Speak again. |
Efficient Causes
When we talk about the 'efficient cause' of something, we are talking about the productive agency or power which gives rise to some change, or brings something into being. Descartes means the Causal Adequacy Principle to be about efficient causation, but it might be on stronger ground if it were about material causation--i.e., about the materials or ingredients out of which something is composed (girders, rivets, and concrete are the material causes of a bridge, but the architect and builders and engineers are the efficient causes of the bridge.) Pierre Gassendi, in the Fifth Objections, says that the Causal Adequacy Principle is on firmer ground if it is a principle about material causation rather than efficient causation
Putting it together
This all comes together in the following claim that Descartes makes at the end of the 14th paragraph:
The notion that ideas are caused is not so hard to swallow, but what is extremely interesting here is the claim that what can serve as the cause of an idea is a function of the content of that idea. What causes your idea of Pegasus must have formal reality, but it must have at least as much formal reality as Pegasus has objective reality. This means, for instance, that a knock on the head with a stone cannot cause your idea of Pegasus. This is because a stone doesn't have enough formal reality. It has more formal reality than the idea has formal reality (because, as we've noted, an idea is only a property and so has very little formal reality), but it has less formal reality than Pegasus as he exists in your idea has objective reality. Bringing this machinery to bear on the causes of ideas is Descartes' contribution to this issue.
Now, the proof that God exists is fairly straightforward: